A Discourse on the
Freedom of the Will
By Ransom Dunn
The F. W. Baptist Church, Boston. 1850Table Of Contents
Preface.
The following discourse was prepared by the request of the Boston Quarterly
Meeting, and but for a request for its publication from the same source would
never have gone beyond the limits of the congregation before which it was presented.
In order to save time and space, quotations have been almost entirely omitted.
But although the language, style, and arrangement, and many of the ideas advanced,
cannot honestly be charged upon any other; yet the writer would here once for
all acknowledge himself indebted to all from whom he could derive any advantage,
especially Edwards, Day, Mahan, and Tappan. Believing that something upon this
subject is greatly needed in our churches, this, with some hesitancy, is submitted
as a kind of substitute for what we need, until a more able pen is employed.
That it may be of some little service to the cause of Christ, and to some few
at least, of those with whom his life and interest from childhood have been
identified is the sincere desire and earnest of the
AUTHOR. Boston, March 1, 1850 FREEDOM OF THE WILL "For
unto whomsoever much is given, of him shall be much required: and
to whom men have committed much, of him they will ask the more." Luke 12:48.
That human obligation is precisely in proportion to human ability, is the doctrine
of this text. This doctrine applied to our relations to the divine government,
constitutes one of the distinguishing peculiarities, and is the occasion of
the distinguishing name, of that portion of the church with which we are connected.
Three questions, however, are necessarily embraced in this subject, and perhaps
were contemplated in the resolution requiring this discourse. Is the will free,
or necessary , in its volitions? Is the atonement limited or unlimited, in
its provisions for man? Is election to eternal life conditional or unconditional
? Are all necessarily embraced in the subject of free salvation ? The discussion
of them all in one discourse would be impossible. I have therefore concluded
to confine myself to the first. And the consideration, even of this topic,
within the narrow limits assigned, will be attended with serious difficulties.
To avoid these difficulties, technical and philosophical terms must be avoided
as far as possible, and such terms, arguments, and illustrations used as will
require the least possible explanation. This course is the more readily adopted
in view of the fact, that a last portion of the field from which the arguments
and illustrations upon this subject are drawn, is open to all, and accessible
by persons of every degree of ability. The supposition that this subject is
so philosophical and metaphysical, as to be above the common mind, is altogether
a mistake. Whether our volition are free or necessary, is a question to be
settled wholly by the development of the mind itself; and therefore, every
individual possesses the volume from which he may read the truth, and the whole
truth, upon this subject. Two positions have been taken respecting volition
and the will.
Some have contended that every volition, choice, or determination, was the
effect of motive, and that motive invariably sustained the relation of cause,
and of necessary causes, to all acts of the will. And, that, in every cause
the existence of the antecedent (motive,) renders the sequent, (volition,)
necessary, and necessarily just what it is.
Others contend that whatever relation motive may sustain to volition, it is
not that of necessary cause. If motive be an antecedent, it is one from which
either of two or more sequents may follow. It is also believed by this cause
of Metaphysicians and Theologians, that motive is not the cause of volition,
unless by motive is understood the power that determines. And that notwithstanding
motive is always present in volition, yet it is the object acted upon and not
the agent that moves the mind. And that man is free in this sense-that at any
given time his volitions are so caused, by the causative principle in his own
mind, that they might not have been, or that they might have been different
from what they are.
This is the doctrine of this discourse. And in its discussion, it
is my design:
I. To answer some of the objections urged against the freedom of the Will.
II. Present some arguments for its support.
III. Give a brief summary of objections to the doctrine of necessity.
Let us proceed then,
I. Answers to some of the Objections which are brought against the position assumed in this discourse.
1. The Metaphysician affirms that everything is either necessary
or contingent. If volition is not necessary, then it is contingent;
and if contingent, then
it occurs by mere chance; and is as liable to be in one
direction as in another, regardless of all influences and motives.
But every effect must have a cause;
volition is an effect, and therefore must have a cause.
If every thing is necessary or contingent, and if contingency implies
the absence of all cause,
then it follows necessarily, if volition be an effect,
it must be necessary, and necessarily just as it is. This is almost
the entire burden of President
Day's work on the Will. In reply, it may be said, that
contingency is not here properly explained. It is not used in opposition
to cause, but in opposition
to necessity. The question is not whether volition is uncaused,
but whether the relation of motive to volition is that of necessary
cause. To affirm
that every thing contingent is without cause, is to destroy
all idea of contingency. Everything is caused but the Deity, and
His existence is certainly necessary,
therefore nothing, upon this hypothesis, can be contingent.
If there may be events, rendered contingent by the possibility
of either of two or more
results from their causes, which we know is possible, then
this objection is groundless.
2. But the Logician applies a part of this objection
in a different manner. If every effect
must have an adequate cause, and if volition be an effect,
then every volition must have an antecedent. And hence all
choice
depends upon pre-existing motive, and the greatest
motive, or, "greatest ap- parent good," is
the cause of every particular volition. This is the sum and substance of Edwards'
"Inquiry on the Will."
(1.) Here again, we have the erroneous assumption, that antecedents and causality,
imply necessity. It is simply saying, that because volitions take place, (for
they must be effects,) therefore they cannot be free, or contingent. It is
begging, or at least overlooking, the entire question in dispute.
(2.) The affirmation, that the greatest motive invariably governs, is a mere
assumption, incapable of proof. We ask, how does any one know that he is governed
by the greatest motive? The answer, and the only answer possible, is, that
he is thus influenced. But, how does he know that he is thus influenced? Because
the greatest motive governs. And thus the assumption is the proof, and the
proof the assumption, and finally they are both assumptions, incapable of any
proof. This is reasoning in a circle with a short curve. It is simply saying
that we know how man is influenced, because we know the nature of the cause;
and we know the nature of the cause, because we know how he is influenced.
(3.) This idea of cause and effect, antecedents and sequences, as thus applied,
would necessarily imply an eternal succession of antecedents, which is an absurdity.
If the volition we now form is caused by a pre-existing motive, that motive
must also have had a cause, and its cause must also have been produced, and
thus you may proceed ad infinitum. It is saying there is a succession of periods,
every one of which had a beginning, and yet one did not begin. A chain of events,
every one of which must have been caused, and yet one (the first) could not
have been caused. And if the objector sees fit to hang the chain upon the volition
of God, he is not at all relieved. For I remark:
(4.) We are not reasoning upon this subject merely in reference to the phenomena
of the human will. The objection refers to volitions and their antecedents,
irrespective of the being in which such volitions take place. Now, if every
volition implies an antecedent motive, in view of which the volition is formed,
and formed necessarily just as it is; then, either God wills without motive,
or else he not only wills in view of motive, but is in each respective volition
governed by a previously existing motive. And, therefore, this difficulty is
only rendered more difficult by referring it to the Deity.
3. But the Theologian urges the foreknowledge of God as an objection to our
position. What God foreknows will come to pass, must necessarily take place;
is the universal objection of all necessitarians, to moral freedom.
(1.) We know of no mode of knowledge which implies causality. The simple perception
or consciousness of an act or event, is in every mind clearly distinct from
the cause or power which produces it. Therefore, whatever degree of certainty
may be affirmed of any event upon the ground of knowledge, its cause must be
looked for somewhere else. If God knows things upon principles entirely different
from any with which man is acquainted, our ignorance of the mode of such knowledge
renders the objection groundless.
(2.) But if our knowledge of future events is analogous to His, divine foreknowledge
can have nothing to do with causality. The Astronomer makes his calculations
respecting the motions and changes of the planets for years to come, and with
mathematical certainty knows and states his conclusions; and yet who believes
that his knowledge has any thing to do with the causality or necessity of such
events? And does any knowledge we have of the future differ from this in this
respect? It may be said, that much if not most of our knowledge of the future
depends upon the knowledge of causes which render the events certain. This
is true, but still every one knows that the knowledge is not the cause, nor
the cause the knowledge; but that they are perfectly distinct. Every child
who knows enough to know that if he thrusts his hand into the fire, it will
be burned, knows too that his knowledge of the fact is not the fire, nor the
power that produces the heat. But if foreknowledge when applied to the divine
character, does not mean the same as when applied to human character, then
what does it mean, but present knowledge?
(3.) God's foreknowledge is not of the same nature with our forecast. All knowledge
is necessarily of two kinds. It is mediate or immediate, viz., we know by direct
perception or consciousness, or else through the medium of an object or evidence,
which lies between us and the object or fact known; e. g., I know there is
such a place as Canton; but, do not know it by direct perception. I know there
is such a place as Boston, upon a different principle. The future or foreknowledge
of the astronomer is through an intermediate object or evidence, and is inferential.
He knows the event because he knows its cause. But his knowledge of the planet
upon which he is now gazing does not thus depend upon previous knowledge or
evidence. He knows its present position and aspect because he sees it regardless
of all causes.
If God is infinite, filling all space, and even filling all duration, there,
can be no object or evidence between him and the object or fact known. All
knowledge, therefore, with him must be immediate and direct. He does not know
an event because something else is known, or because of the knowledge of some
antecedent cause; but by direct perception. And all events, whether caused
by his own power or the agency of others, are known, not in consequence of
necessary cause, but simply because they occur. Things are known, not because
they must be, but because they are. And in knowing our volitions, he knows
them as our volitions; and because they are put forth, and not because they
are made certain by his determinations or decrees.
Again, it should be remembered that all knowledge is present knowledge. The
fore and after, which we apply to knowledge, have reference to the object of
knowledge, not the knowledge. If we know of an event that occurred yesterday,
we know it now. Memory brings up the event now, and makes it a present knowledge.
If we possessed the power of prescience, sustaining the same relation to the
future that memory does to the past, the knowledge would be present, and the
one would have as little to do with the causality or necessity of events as
the other. God's foreknowledge, then, although it makes it certain that an
event does occur, no more makes it certain that such an event might not have
been otherwise, than my knowledge of your presence here to day makes it certain
that you could not have been elsewhere. You could have been elsewhere, and
then the knowledge of your position would have been accordingly. Our actions
might have been different from what they are, and God's knowledge would have
been according to the facts in the case.
The idea that simple knowledge implies necessity with respect to cause, is
not according to sound philosophy, common sense, nor the Bible.
II. Some positive arguments in support of the doctrine of "FREE-WILL."
1. We will listen to the voice of consciousness. By
consciousness is here understood, not the power which
knows, but the recognizing of the knowledge. It is
that
field upon which the mind, on the one hand, and the external
world, on the other meets. We are not conscious of
anything with- out the mind; but in
perceiving objects, sensations are produced of which we
are conscious. We are not conscious even of the powers
of mind, as such, but these powers produce
sensations of which we are conscious. This field of sensation
or consciousness, then, is the ground of all oar knowledge.
No external object is known unless
there exists such a correlation between the object and
the mind as to produce sensation. And no power of mind
is known except by its action, which produces
sensation. It is evident, therefore, that our knowledge
of the mind, and especially of the will, must be derived
from this source.
If we investigate this field, I think we shall perceive
that the sensations from objects without, and the mind
within, clearly indicate the possibility
of our volitions, at any given time, being different from
what they are and that it is only upon this principle that
we have any idea of right and wrong
in character, or of praise-worthiness or blame-worthiness,
in ourselves or others.
But there are some general developments of common consciousness
upon this subject.
(1.) Language comprises but signs of ideas; and any
term or form of expression, supposes the
pre-existence of the idea expressed. In every language and
tongue spoken, there are words and phrases, implying
the freedom of the
will. Thus
said, "We ought not to have done thus," or "We ought to have determined upon
a different course," viz. If necessitarianism be true, we
ought not to have complied with an eternal immutable, divine
law,
which God
himself could not
have broken; or we ought to have violated such a law. So
when we express regret or astonishment that volitions in
ourselves
or others
should
have been as they
are, we use language unmeaning, nonsensical, and sinful,
if they, were determined by the Almighty, and could not have
been
otherwise.
The
same is true of all
(2.) Not only the language, but the laws of all nations,
civilized or barbarous, indicate most conclusively the decision
of consciousness upon this subject.
Do they not all proceed upon the supposition that when a
subject determines to do right, he might have determined
to do wrong, and that when he determines
to do wrong he might have determined to do right.
(3.) And, does not the justification or condemnation others
show most conclusively, the position of consciousness upon
this question?
The disposition to justify and condemn seems to arise instinctively,
as from a principle of our natures. Even before language
is learned, the infant mind
develops this disposition. And just in proportion as mind
is developed, distinctions are made between the intelligent
and unintelligent portions of creation, and
praise or blame awarded to the former and none to the latter.
Why this disposition, and why this distinction between voluntary
and material agency, if all things,
and all things alike, are governed by the same unalterable
laws of necessity? And why has God thus made one portion
of creation to oppose and find fault
with another, if the same necessity governs the action and
tendency of both?
2. Notwithstanding this is purely a psychological subject,
and should be treated as such, yet there are certain necessary
logical deductions arising from the
two systems now under consideration, which will aid us materially
in deciding upon their respective merits.
What Are the necessary consequences of necessitarianism ?
If volition is necessitated, and can in no given case be
different from what it is, then there can be no responsibility
attending volition. If we cannot
hold the knife responsible for stabbing a man, while the
hand which grasps the knife and directs the blow is held
by another, how can we hold the man
responsible while the power which constitutes his agency
is held and controlled by force beyond his agency? We hold
a man responsible for presenting motives
even when they do not prevail. Where, then, does responsibility
rest when in every case, and necessarily in every case, volition
is as the motive?--upon
our actions, here effects, or upon the actual cause of that
action, the author of the motive?
It has been said that responsibility rests upon natural,
not moral ability. But Edwards himself tells us that the
difference between natural and moral
ability does not consist in the nature of the necessity,
but simply in the terms thus related. Moral necessity referring
to volitions and their cause,
motives; and natural necessity, to the connection between
physical causes and their effects. Natural and moral ability
and inability differ then only in
the same way. Natural inability, is inability to do what
we will; moral inability, an inability to will. There is
no difference in the necessity. The one is as
fatal as the other, and implies as little responsibility.
Now, either. there is, or there is not any occasion for this
distinction between natural and moral
ability. If there is not such occasion, and if volition is
necessary, then the same fatal necessity pervades alike the
whole universe; and there is as
much responsibility resting upon the physical as the moral
world. But, if there is an occasion for such distinction,
then, to base moral obligation upon natural
or physical ability, is as inconsistent as to require a man
naturally blind to see, because, forsooth, he could hear-or
to require a man to move an arm
which he never possessed, because he has a foot. If a man
is not the cause of his own volitions, and in that sense
possessed of moral ability, he cannot
be responsible. Moral responsibility cannot rest upon natural
ability.
But again, motive is unintelligent and irresponsible; and,
therefore, the Author of motive is the only being in the
universe who is responsible; and he is responsible
for every action. But if He determines our volitions, He
thus determines in view of motive. For upon the hypothesis
now before us, a volition in the Eternal
Mind, without an antecedent motive, would be just as impossible
as in our own. Therefore there never was a divine volition
without a pre-existing motive.
Hence there was a time when there was no force in the universe,
but the force of motive; and when there either was no God,
or else no active God. If we take
one horn of the dilemma, and say there was a God, but a God
without volition, and consequently without activity or character,
we have the Pantheist's God.
If we take the other, and affirm that previous to volition
there was no intelligent God, we have the God of the Atheist.
In either case, the universe presents
but a vast blind machine, driven by fate through the immensity
,of space and duration.
Attending these necessary results, there are several inferences
which might be drawn; but one of which, however, can with
due regard to our assigned limits,
be here admitted.
If the above mentioned hypothesis and its necessary consequences
be correct, then all distinctions between good and evil are
hypothetical and imaginary.
Both are in compliance with fixed, immutable law. Hence all
distinctions between vice and virtue, and all restraints
or encouragements, family, civil or religious,
growing out of these distinctions, are false and vain.
But what are the deductions from the supposition that the
will is self determining? At all events, the difficulties
cannot be greater, the consequences more absurd,
than those which arise from the opposite system. It cannot
be an absurdity, for the practice of all men, in all the
common affairs of life, has been based
upon this freedom, and common consciousness and spontaneous
convictions have always sustained this doctrine.
Upon the supposition of its truth, man at once appears an
accountable being; he himself, and no other one, being responsible
for his volitions. He is thus
rendered a fit subject of moral government. The institution
of human governments, and the organization of the family,
with all the voluntary relations and influences
growing out of them, are thus made legitimate and reasonable.
Language and the most plain decisions of consciousness, which
would otherwise present the
most inexplicable difficulties, are thus rendered plain and
simple. The atonement, with all the means of grace, the disciplinary
influences of providence, and
all human efforts for the change of character, which would
otherwise be but a solemn farce, at once appear necessary
and consistent.
3. But the practical influences of the two systems must not
be passed over.
It will not be assumed that all believers in necessitarianism
are wicked men, nor that all believers in moral freedom are
good. There are many exceptions
upon both sides, and many whose character is not materially
affected by any particular views entertained respecting this
question. But still, it seems
to me, that there are certain facts connected with this aspect
of the subject, which deserve our serious consideration.
And,
(1st.) Invariably, those who have denied human responsibility
and accountability, have based that denial upon the doctrine
of necessity. But who ever heard of
an individual believing in the freedom of the will, as above
explained, who denied man's accountability? Such an instance
never was known.
(2d.) Almost all of the greatest errors in religion and morals,
have been advocated upon the ground of moral necessity, and
many of them based exclusively upon
this theory.
This is the beginning and the end with the Atheist. It is
the sum total of the Pantheist's scheme. And the Deist, Universalist,
Fatalist and Antinomian,
in defending their respective systems, are equally dependent
upon the supposition, that whatever is, is so of necessity;
and that therefore whatever is, is right.
When we reflect, that the doctrine we are now controverting
is not an incidental item in these systems, but one of the
fundamental assumptions upon which their
advocates all base them, and that they are not defended without
this assumption, are we not forced to the conclusion that
in its practical result there is a
refutation of all claims to truth; unless indeed, these systems
be true. But has the doctrine of freedom ever been used for
any such purpose? If so, I am
not aware of the fact.
(3.) And is it not an undeniable fact, that the most immoral
and irreligious, are generally warm advocates of the doctrine
of necessity; and especially when
pressed upon moral or religious obligations. I know it is
said, they only fly to this for a refuge. But this is making
a great admission, namely, that the
system constitutes a very convenient garb for such characters.
Can a doctrine so peculiarly adapted to such a work, and
so generally associated with such
characters, be true, even though many of the best men of
the world have believed it?
But do men ever apologize for their crimes upon the ground
that they are free agents, capable of choosing a different
course, and responsible for not doing
so?
(4.) Another significant fact which bears upon this subject,
is seen in the course pursued by the best classes of those
opposed to our position.
Is it not universally known, that in their efforts for changing
the hearts and characters of men--for promoting morality
and religion, they leave entirely
out of sight their peculiar views upon this question, and
address themselves to common sense and common consciousness.
Does the moralist in his efforts to reform the blasphemer
or nebriate, begin with an essay upon moral necessity, and
after convincing his disciples that
his volitions could not have been different from what they
are, and that any change in his future course depends exclusively
upon motives beyond his control,
and that such motives win as certainly control him as the
unobstructed weight falls to the earth, proceed to urge a
change of life? None labor in his
way. And to pursue such a course would exhibit as little
claim to sanity, as an effort to persuade the Mississippi
to just roll back from its mouth over
the falls of St. Anthony.
And what is the course of the pastor when laboring
with an impenitent sinner, or in a season
of special religious interest in his congregation? Is
not
the instruction and preaching at such times so
emphatically "free-will" that the
"Free-willer" is perfectly satisfied?
Does not this fact go to show most conclusively, that our
opponents themselves have no confidence in the practical
influence of their doctrine, and especially
when any great practical interest is at stake? The facts
that convicted men generally urge this doctrine as an apology,
for impenitence, and that nine-tenths
of all who fall into final religious despair, do so through
its influence, and other circumstances indicating its practical
influence we have not room
for discussing.
4. But the belief that any such power as will is possessed
by man is to my mind an evidence of its freedom.
As above remarked, we know of no powers of mind but by their
action. If volition is but a necessary sequence of an antecedent
correlation between intelligent
sensibility and an external object, then nothing more is
brought into action than intelligence and sensibility. This
phenomenon is to be accounted for,
by supposing the existence of these powers, but no other.
As well might a man suppose that because be feels a sensation
from the fingers of his hand, that
therefore, he has one upon the back of his hand; or that
because he has eyes, that therefore he must possess some
other organs differing entirely from these,
as to suppose that because he is conscious of phenomena resulting
from reason and sensitivity, that therefore he has a will.
I know that consciousness will
here be appealed to, and we shall be told that every man
knows that he has a will. This is admitted and this is the
strength of the argument. Man knows
he has a will. But he must know this by phenomena arising
directly from such a faculty, differing from that arising
from the sensibility or reason.
If volition be necessary, it is but the action of the sensibility,
and can in no sense be any evidence of the existence of any
other faculty.
This argument is presented with the more confidence, in view
of the fact that Edwards makes no distinction between the
will and sensibility. He refers to
but two grand divisions of the mind; the knowing and the
attractive powers. Under this last division, he classes desires,
in affections, volitions and
every other development of will or sensibility-and then makes
volition a result from relation between an object and these
powers, thus tacitly admitting that
his theory virtually destroys all distinct idea of the will
and makes it sensitivity, or mental attraction, If any man
can show how he knows that he has a will by
such sensations, let him attempt it. And if the universal
belief that such a power is possessed does not result from
phenomena which can result only from
the freedom of the will, I know not where it could have originated!
5. But the last class of argument, to which I refer, is drawn
from the Scriptures. But here it may be observed, the Bible
is not given for a scientific text book,
nor for a system of philosophy. Those natural common matters
of fact with which we are able to become acquainted by other
means, are there taken for granted.
That man has some knowledge is every where assumed. The word
of God no where tells us the number or uses of the senses.
Neither does it teach mental philosophy,
nor directly discuss the subject now under consideration.
Mental or psychological facts must be proved from the Bible
just as we should prove the existence or
use of the senses, or any other physical fact. We must prove
the freedom of the will just as we should prove its existence.
Were we to attempt either,
we should inquire, what does the Bible every where assume
respecting this subject? Do references to individuals and
special circumstances throw any light upon
it? What, respecting the question is implied in the doctrines
of Christianity?
If then, we throw an eye upon the general surface of the
sacred page, and look at its history and laws, its promises
and threatenings, its revelations and
prophecies does not every reference to human nature or character
assume the freedom of the will? Nothing is more clearly assumed
than this.
And if we look at specific references to times, persons,
and events, do we not see the same assumption? Do not all
these references to times of prosperity
or adversity, to individuals or nations, to events, providential
or human, imply the freedom of the will?
Pharaoh, Jacob, and a few others, have been suggested as
exceptions. These subjects more properly belong to the questions
respecting election and the
atonement. And, therefore, without pausing to give specific
explanations respecting the texts referred to, it may be
said:
(1.) That these are isolated cases. Providing that unusual
and even compulsory influences were in these few instances
exerted, it would no more prove the
general necessity of volition, than miracles prove that God
can work in no other way.
(2.) These cases have nothing to do with specific purposes,
or personal character. They refer to general positions, of
nations or individuals, and have no more
to do with the liberty or necessity of the will, than a residence
in Europe or America.
But what is implied in the doctrines of the Bible.
Take for instance the fall of man. How did
Adam fall? He yielded to the greatest motive, "the greatest
apparent good," says the Calvinist. Then, one of two things must have been
true. Either there actually was more "good" connected with
sin than holiness; or else his mind, as it came from God,
was so constituted
that it was more
easily influenced in that direction than the other. Let him
take which horn of the dilemma he may, the conclusion is
inevitable, that
God
intended, determined,
and directly caused that event, and all the guilt and misery
arising
there from. But the fall of man implies no such thing. He
was free, not as the water
to run down hill, but free to choose or refuse the motives
And respecting the atonement. Why is it given and adapted
to man, and not to other portions of creation, if all are
governed by the same law of necessity?
How can we account for the change which is there contemplated
in man's character, circumstances and prospects, if his will
is not free? Indeed, God cannot contemplate
any change, by an atonement or otherwise, in man's character
or relations without a change in himself, unless man is capable
of causing a change in himself.
Hence the doctrines of pardon and regeneration, as well as
the doctrine of atonement, implies the truth of our position.
So does every doctrine of the
Bible.
But we can notice but one more. Look at the judgement.
What of all the warnings and appeals in view
of it, what of all the solemn attending circumstances,
and what of the judgment itself, if man is to be judged upon
the
same principle with matter? And what shall we think
of the
character of the judge, if he is
not judged upon the same principle, if he is here governed
upon the same principle? And here let it be remembered
that
the advocates of the doctrine of necessary
volition do not claim that there is any difference between
moral and physical necessity in the nature of the
relation.
They
affirm that the necessity is
precisely the same, and that the terms refer to the objects
related, and not to the degree or nature of the
necessity. How,
if this be true, could God be
just and judge the world? If man's volitions and actions
are all,
invariably and necessarily, governed by motives
which God himself controls, how,
while sentence is pronounced against a sinner,
could the angels sing, " Holy, holy,
holy, Lord God Almighty?" Could the inhabitants of heaven say, "Alleluia," while
the wicked are "driven away in their wickedness," "and the smoke of their torment
ascendeth up for ever and ever." Can we force the hand of
a child into the flames, and then punish him for his folly?
Can
the universe
say,
Amen, to the
judgments of God, if he forces our volitions, by overpowering
motives, and then punishes for these volitions? The judgment
in every aspect
most clearly
implies that man's volitions are as much his own as his actions,
and that he is at liberty in his volitions to such an extent,
that he is
not only the cause
of them, but at any given time they might be different from
what they are. Indeed, it seems to me impossible that any,
man could
ever reconcile
the doctrine
of a judgment with the doctrine of necessity; and I do not
wonder that many believers in the latter doctrine have denied
the former.
Having
endeavored
to answer some of the most prominent objections against the
freedom of the will, and presented a few of the many arguments
in favor
of this important
doctrine, let us conclude:
III. A brief summary and repetition of our objections to the opposite sysem.
1. It makes God a tyrant. He requires one thing and
then, with a fatal moral necessity, impels man
in an opposite
direction, and then punishes him for
not acting contrary to the "greatest apparent good," which
is a work that God himself, even, as our opponents affirm,
cannot
2. It makes God contradict himself. He commands one thing,
and then with another will, (for it cannot be the same,)
absolutely, by moral force, effects their
violation.
3. It makes even God a being of necessity, and dependent
for his being or capability of action, upon something prior
to himself.
4. It makes him the author of all sin. No sin, is committed
according to this theory, but in accordance with the greatest
motive; and he governs these motives.
This is especially true in the case of our first parents,
and of the fallen angels. Taking the cause of their transgression
out of themselves, it necessarily
leaves it in God.
5. It destroys all idea of probation. What idea of trial
can be attached to a class of beings who have no control
over themselves, or to a state where
every action is necessarily as it is, and could not have
been otherwise?
6. It destroys all human responsibility. All who deny accountability
do so upon this ground; and a large proportion of those who
attempt to apologize
for neglect of known duty, urge the same plea.
7. It destroys all distinction between vice and virtue. The
one is as necessary and undeniable, and as much in accordance
with God's will, as the other.
8. It is the principal ingredient in some of the worst errors
which ever cursed the earth.
9. It mystifies the gospel, rendering it contradictory; and
thus produces skepticism. Who ever heard of a man turning
from religions views or influences, to infidelity,
without first embracing necessitarianism ?
10. It frequently produces despair in anxious minds; and
in this way is the cause of a total neglect of the gospel,
or, what is more common, an apology
for impenitence.
11. It is generally believed by the worst of men, and made
an apology for their crimes.
12. It is not congenial with the spirit of reform, of revivals,
and of deep piety. Any of its advocates are reformers, revivalists,
and deeply pious men.
But, in their efforts for reforms and revivals, and in their
most devotional exercises, they act as though they could
act, and forget all necessity back
of the will.
Brethren, we love reform. We wish to see the wicked
forsake his way, and the unrighteous man
his thoughts. We wish to see the inebriate restored,
and the
slave set at liberty. We love the spirit of revival. We
wish to see the open gates of Zion thronged with anxious
inquirers,
saying "what shall we do to
be saved." As we feel for these interests and sympathize
with suffering humanity, and as we long for the salvation
of deathless
souls,
let us urge the claims
of God upon man's free-will. Standing still under the banner
of Christ as unfurled by our revered fathers in the gospel,
let us
walk worthy
of the name whereby
we have been called; and cheerfully discharge those obligations
for the neglect of which we acknowledge ourselves without excuse.