Skeletons of a Course of
Theological Lectures
By Charles G. Finney
Lecture III.
Introductory Lecture.--No. 3.
1. Without correct knowledge on this subject
our speculations will be at random.
2. The ridiculous credulity
of some, and the no less ridiculous
incredulity of others, are owing to ignorance, or a disregard
of the fundamental laws of evidence. E.g.: Mormonism
is ridiculous credulity, founded in utter ignorance or a
disregard of the first
principles of evidence in relation to the kind and degree
of testimony demanded to establish anything that claims to
be a
revelation from God.
Every form of religious scepticism, on the other hand, is ridiculous incredulity, founded in ignorance, or a disregard of the fundamental laws of evidence, as will be shown in its place.
1. Evidence is that which elucidates and enables
the mind to apprehend truth.
2. Proof is that degree of evidence
that warrants or demands
belief--that does or ought to produce conviction.
3. Every degree
of evidence is not proof. Every degree of light upon a subject
is evidence. But that only is proof which under
the circumstances can give reasonable satisfaction.
This must depend upon the nature of the thing to be proved.
1. Consciousness may be appealed to upon questions
that are within its reach, or on questions of experience, but
not on other
questions.
2. Sense may be appealed to on questions within the
reach of our senses, but not on other questions.
3. The existence
of God must be proved by his works, as an appeal
to the Bible to settle this question would be assuming
both the fact of his existence, and that the Bible is his word.
4.
The Divine authority of the Bible, or of any book or thing
that claims to be a revelation from God, demands some kind
of evidence that none but God can give. Miracles, are one of
the
most natural and impressive kinds. Prophesy another.
5. Without
God's own testimony, all other evidence would be uncertain
and unsatisfactory upon such a question.
6. Appeals may also
properly be made to such other evidences,
external and internal, as might be reasonably expected
if the revelation in question were really from God.
7. As the
universe is a revelation of God, we may legitimately
wander into every department of nature, science, and grace,
for testimony upon theological subjects.
8. Different questions,
must however draw their evidences from
different departments of revelation. Some from his works
and providence, others from his word, and others still from
all these
together.
KINDS OF EVIDENCE.
1. No impossible or unreasonable kind is to
be expected, e.g.: The evidence of sense is not to be demanded
or expected when
the thing to be proved is not an object of or within the
reach of sensation.
2. Nor of consciousness when the question
is not one of experience
and does not belong to the exercises of our own minds.
3. It
is a sound rule that the best evidence in kind shall be adduced,
that the nature of the case admits: for instance,
(1.) Oral testimony is not admissible where written testimony may be had to the same point.
(2.) Of course oral traditions are not to be received where there is written history to the same point.
(3.) But oral testimony is admissible in the absence of written, as then, it is the best that the nature of the case admits.
(4.) So oral traditions may be received to establish points of antiquity, in the absence of contemporary history.
(5.) Any book claiming to be a revelation from God, should, in some way, bear his own seal as a kind of evidence at once possible and demanded by the nature of the subject.
DEGREE OF EVIDENCE.
1. Not, in general, demonstration; as this
would be inconsistent with a state of probation under a moral
government.
2. Not, in general, such a degree of evidence
as to preclude
the possibility of cavil or evasion, for the same reason.
But,
1. Such an amount of evidence on all fundamental questions
as to afford reasonable satisfaction to an honest and inquiring
mind.
2. Such an amount of evidence upon the face of creation
itself as should gain the general assent of mankind to
the
facts of
the Divine existence and of human accountability.
3. That
the evidence could be more or less, Latent, Patent, Direct,
Inferential,
Incidental, Full, and Unanswerable according
to its relative importance in the system of Divine truth.
NOT FATAL.
1. Not when they are not well established
by proof.
2. Not when the truth of the objection may consist
with the truth of the proposition which it is intended
to overthrow.
3. Not when the affirmative proposition is
conclusively established
by testimony, although we may be unable to discover
the consistency
of the proposition with the objection.
4. Not always fatal
because unanswerable.
BUT AN OBJECTION IS FATAL,
1. When
it is an unquestionable
reality, and plainly incompatible with the truth of
the proposition against which it lies.
2. When the higher
probability is in
its favour.
3. When the objection is established by
a
higher kind or degree
of evidence than the proposition to which it is
opposed. E.g. Consciousness is the highest kind of evidence:
an
objection founded
in, or supported by consciousness will set aside other
testimony.
4. The testimony of sense is not always conclusive
in the face
of other testimony, and an objection founded in,
and supported by sensation is not always fatal.
5. An
objection is fatal,
when it fully proves that the proposition in question
is
not merely above, but plainly contrary to the
affirmations of reason.
This depends upon their nature.
1. If mere
cavils without reason or proof, they may remain unnoticed.
2.
So, if they appear reasonable, if proved, and are yet without
proof, we are not called on to reply.
3. We are not bound
to explain the objection and show that it is consistent with
the proposition against which it is alleged,
but simply that if a fact, it may be consistent with
it. It then rests with our opponent to show that if it might
be consistent
with the proposition, yet as a matter of fact it is not.
4.
No objection is competent to set aside first truths, such
as that a whole is equal to all its parts. A part is
less than a whole etc.
5. No objection can set aside the direct
testimony of consciousness.
6. Nor can an objection set aside
the unambiguous testimony
of God.
7. First, and self evident truths, the affirmations
of reason, consciousness, and the testimony of God, can never
conflict with
each other.
8. There is always a fallacy in whatever is flatly
inconsistent with either of these.
1. Always on him who makes the affirmation,
unless his affirmation is sufficiently manifest without proof.
2.
The onus probandi lies with the affirmative until the evidence
fairly amounts to proof in the absence of opposing testimony.
3.
When the affirmative evidence amounts to proof, the onus
is upon the objector.
4. Every kind and degree of evidence
that may as well consist with the negative as the affirmative
of the proposition to be
proved, leaves the onus unchanged.
5. When the evidence, or
an argument, or an objection proves too much, as well as
when it proves too little, it leaves the
onus unchanged.
6. If an objection needs proof, the onus lies
upon the objector.
1. Proof or argument, must commence where
uncertainty commences.
2. Hence, all argument and proof take
for granted such truths as need no proof but are either axioms,
self evident truths,
or such as are already sufficiently apparent.